History of philosophy in Poland

Contents

The history of philosophy in Poland parallels the evolution of philosophy in Europe in general. Polish philosophy drew upon the broader currents of European philosophy, and in turn contributed to their growth. Among the most momentous Polish contributions were made in the thirteenth century by the Scholastic philosopher and scientist Witelo; and in the sixteenth century, by the Renaissance polymath Nicolaus Copernicus.[1]

Subsequently, the Polish-Lithuanian Commonwealth partook in the intellectual ferment of the Enlightenment, which for the multi-ethnic Commonwealth ended not long after the partitions and political annihilation that would last for the next 123 years, until the collapse of the three partitioning empires in World War I.

The period of Messianism, between the November 1830 and January 1863 Uprisings, reflected European Romantic and Idealist trends, as well as a Polish yearning for political resurrection. It was a period of maximalist metaphysical systems.

The collapse of the January 1863 Uprising prompted an agonizing reappraisal of Poland's situation. Poles gave up their earlier practice of "measuring their resources by their aspirations," and buckled down to hard work and study. "[A] Positivist," wrote the novelist Bolesław Prus' friend, Julian Ochorowicz, was "anyone who bases assertions on verifiable evidence; who does not express himself categorically about doubtful things, and does not speak at all about those that are inaccessible."[2]

The twentieth century brought a new quickening to Polish philosophy. There was growing interest in western philosophical currents. Rigorously trained Polish philosophers made substantial contributions to specialized fields—to psychology, the history of philosophy, the theory of knowledge, and especially mathematical logic.[3] Jan Łukasiewicz gained world fame with his concept of many-valued logic and his "Polish notation."[4] Alfred Tarski's work in truth theory won him world renown.[5]

After World War II, for over four decades, world-class Polish philosophers and historians of philosophy such as Władysław Tatarkiewicz continued their work, often in the face of adversities occasioned by the dominance of a politically enforced official philosophy. The phenomenologist Roman Ingarden did influential work in esthetics and in a Husserl-style metaphysics; his student Karol Wojtyła acquired a unique influence on the world stage as Pope John Paul II.

Scholasticism

The formal history of philosophyin Polandmay be said to have begun in the fifteenth century, following the revival of the University of Krakówby King Władysław II Jagiełłoin 1400.[6]The true beginnings of Polish philosophy, however, reach back to the thirteenth century and Witelo(ca. 1230 – ca. 1314), a Silesianborn to a Polish mother and a Thuringiansettler, a contemporary of Thomas Aquinaswho had spent part of his life in Italyat centers of the highest intellectual culture. In addition to being a philosopher, he was a scientistwho specialized in optics. His famous treatise, Perspectiva, while drawing on the ArabicBook of Opticsby Alhazen, was unique in Latinliterature,[7]and in turn helped inspire Roger Bacon's best work, Part V of his Opus maius, "On Perspectival Science," as well as his supplementary treatise On the Multiplication of Vision.[8]Witelo's Perspectivaadditionally made important contributions to psychology: it held that visionper seapprehends only colorsand lightwhile all else, particularly the distance and size of objects, is established by means of associationand unconscious deduction.[6]Witelo's concept of beingwas one rare in the Middle Ages, neither Augustinianas among conservatives nor Aristotelianas among progressives, but Neoplatonist. It was an emanationistconcept that held radiationto be the prime characteristic of being, and ascribed to radiation the nature of light. This "metaphysic of light" inclined Witelo to opticalresearch, or perhaps vice versahis optical studies led to his metaphysic.[9]According to the Polish historian of philosophy, Władysław Tatarkiewicz, no Polish philosopher since Witelohas enjoyed so eminent a European standing as this thinker who belonged, in a sense, to the prehistoryof Polish philosophy.[10]From the beginning of the fifteenth century, Polish philosophy, centered at Kraków University, pursued a normal course. It no longer harbored exceptional thinkers such as Witelo, but it did feature representatives of all wings of mature Scholasticism, via antiquaas well as via moderna.[10]The first of these to reach Kraków was via moderna, then the more widespread movement in Europe.[11]In physics, logicand ethics, Terminism(Nominalism) prevailed in Kraków, under the influence of the FrenchScholastic, Jean Buridan(died ca. 1359), who had been rectorof the University of Parisand an exponent of views of William of Ockham. Buridan had formulated the theoryof "impetus"—the forcethat causes a body, once set in motion, to persist in motion—and stated that impetus is proportionalto the speedof, and amount of mattercomprising, a body: Buridan thus anticipated Galileoand Isaac Newton. His theory of impetus was momentous in that it also explained the motions of celestial bodieswithout resort to the spirits"intelligentiae"—to which the Peripatetics(followers of Aristotle) had ascribed those motions.[12]At Kraków, physics was now expounded by (St.) Jan Kanty(1390–1473), who developed this concept of "impetus."[10]A general trait of the Kraków Scholasticswas a provlivity for compromise—for reconciling Nominalismwith the older tradition. For example, the Nominalist, Benedict Hesse, while in principle accepting the theory of impetus, did not apply it to the heavenly spheres.[10]In the second half of the fifteenth century, at Kraków, via antiquabecame dominant. Nominalismretreated, and the old Scholasticismtriumphed.[11]In this period, Thomismhad its chief center at Cologne, whence it influenced Kraków. Cologne, formerly the home ground of Albertus Magnus, had preserved Albert's mode of thinking. Thus the Cologne philosophers formed two wings, the Thomist and Albertist, and even Cologne's Thomists showed Neoplatonisttraits characteristic of Albert, affirming emanation, a hierarchyof being, and a metaphysicof light.[10]The chief Kraków adherents of the Cologne-style Thomism included Jan of Głogów(ca. 1445–1507) and Jakub of Gostynin(ca. 1454–1506). Another, purer teacher of Thomism was Michał Falkenerof Wrocław(ca. 1450–1534).[13]Almost at the same time, Scotismappeared in Poland, having been brought from Parisfirst by Michał Twaróg of Bystrzyków(ca. 1450–1520). Twaróg had studied at Paris in 1473–77, in the period when, following the anathematizationof the Nominalists(1473), the Scotist school was there enjoying its greatest triumphs. A prominent student of Twaróg's, Jan of Stobnica(ca. 1470–1519), was already a moderate Scotist who took account of the theories of the Ockhamists, Thomistsand Humanists.[14]When Nominalismwas revived in western Europeat the turn of the sixteenth century, particularly thanks to Jacques Lefèvre d'Étaples(Faber Stapulensis), it presently reappeared in Krakówand began taking the upper hand there once more over Thomismand Scotism. It was reintroduced particularly by Lefèvre's pupil, Jan Szylling, a native of Kraków who had studied at Paris in the opening years of the sixteenth century. Another follower of Lefèvre's was Grzegorz of Stawiszyn, a Kraków professor who, beginning in 1510, published the Frenchman's works at Kraków.[14]Thus Polandhad made her appearance as a separate philosophical center only at the turn of the fifteenth century, at a time when the creative period of Scholasticphilosophy had already passed. Throughout the fifteenth century, Poland harbored all the currents of Scholasticism. The advent of Humanismin Poland would find a Scholasticism more vigorous than in other countries. Indeed, Scholasticism would survive the 16th and 17th centuries and even part of the 18th at Krakówand Wilno Universitiesand at numerous Jesuit, Dominicanand Franciscancolleges.[15]To be sure, in the sixteenth century, with the arrival of the Renaissance, Scholasticismwould enter upon a decline; but during the 17th century's Counter-reformation, and even into the early 18th century, Scholasticism would again become Poland's chief philosophy.[16]

Renaissance

The spirit of Humanism, which had reached Poland by the middle of the fifteenth century, was not very "philosophical." Rather, it lent its stimulus to linguisticstudies, politicalthought, and scientificresearch. But these manifested a philosophical attitude different from that of the previous period.[17]Empiricalnatural sciencehad flourished at Krakówas early as the fifteenth century, side by side with speculative philosophy. The most perfect product of this blossoming was Nicolaus Copernicus(1473–1543, Polish: Mikołaj Kopernik). He was not only a scientist but a philosopher. According to Tatarkiewicz, he may have been the greatest—in any case, the most renowned—philosopher that Poland ever produced. He drew the inspiration for his cardinal discovery from philosophy; he had become acquainted through Marsilio Ficinowith the philosophies of Platoand the Pythagoreans; and through the writings of the philosophers Ciceroand Plutarchhe had learned about the ancientswho had declared themselves in favor of the Earth's movement.[18]Copernicus may also have been influenced by Kraków philosophy: during his studies there, Terministphysicshad been taught, with special emphasis on "impetus." His own thinking was guided by philosophical considerations. He arrived at the heliocentricthesis (as he was to write in a youthful treatise) "ratione postea equidem sensu": it was not observationbut the discovery of a logicalcontradictionin Ptolemy's system, that served him as a point of departure that led to the new astronomy. In his dedication to Pope Paul III, he submitted his work for judgment by "philosophers."[19]In its turn, Copernicus' theory transformed man's view of the structure of the universe, and of the place held in it by the earth and by man, and thus attained a far-reaching philosophical importance.[19]Copernicus was involved not only in natural scienceand natural philosophybut also—by his studies in the theory of valueand money(see "Gresham's Law")—in the philosophy of man.[19]In the early sixteenth century, Plato, who had become a model for philosophy in Italy, especially in MediceanFlorence, was represented in Polandin some ways by Adam of Łowicz, author of Conversations about Immortality.[19]Generally speaking, though, Poland remained Aristotelian. Sebastian Petrycyof Pilzno(1554–1626) laid stress, in the theory of knowledge, on experimentand induction; and in psychology, on feelingand will; while in politicshe preached democraticideas. Petrycy's central feature was his linking of philosophical theory with the requirements of practical national life. In 1601-18, a period when translationsinto modern languageswere still rarities, he accomplished Polish translations of Aristotle's practical works. With Petrycy, vernacularPolish philosophical terminologybegan to develop not much later than did the French and German.[20]Yet another Renaissancecurrent, the new Stoicism, was represented in Poland by Jakub Górski(ca. 1525–1585), author of a famous Dialectic(1563) and of many works in grammar, rhetoric, theologyand sociology. He tended toward eclecticism, attempting to reconcile the Stoicswith Aristotle.[21]A later, purer representative of Stoicismin Poland was Adam Burski(ca. 1560–1611), author of a Dialectica Ciceronis(1604) boldly proclaiming Stoic sensualismand empiricismand—before Francis Bacon—urging the use of inductive method.[21]A star among the pleiadeof progressive politicalphilosophers during the Polish Renaissancewas Andrzej Frycz Modrzewski(1503–72), who advocated on behalf of equalityfor all before the law, the accountability of monarchand governmentto the nation, and social assistance for the weak and disadvantaged.[22]His chief work was De Republica emendanda(On Reform of the Republic, 1551–54). Another notable political thinker was Wawrzyniec Grzymała Goślicki(1530–1607), best known in Poland and abroad for his book De optimo senatore(The Accomplished Senator, 1568). It propounded the view—which for long got the book banned in England, as subversive of monarchy—that a ruler may legitimately govern only with the sufferance of the people.[23]After the first decades of the 17th century, the wars, invasionsand internal dissensionsthat beset the Polish-Lithuanian Commonwealth, brought a decline in philosophy. If in the ensuing period there was independent philosophical thought, it was among the religious dissenters, particularly the Polish Arians,[24]also known variously as Antitrinitarians, Socinians, and Polish Brethren—forerunners of the Britishand AmericanSocinians, Unitariansand Deistswho were to figure prominently in the intellectual and political currents of the 17th, 18th and 19th centuries.[25]The Polish dissenterscreated an original ethicaltheory radically condemning evil and violence. Centers of intellectual life such as that at Lesznohosted notable thinkers such as the Czechpedagogue, Jan Amos Komensky(Comenius), and the Pole, Jan Jonston. Jonston was tutor and physician to the Leszczyńskifamily, a devotee of Bacon and experimental knowledge, and author of Naturae constantia, published in Amsterdamin 1632, whose geometricalmethod and naturalistic, almost pantheisticconcept of the world may have influenced Benedict Spinoza.[24]The Leszczyńskifamily itself would produce an 18th-century Polish-Lithuanianking, Stanisław Leszczyński(1677–1766; reigned in the Polish-Lithuanian Commonwealth1704-11 and again 1733-36), "le philosophe bienfaisant" ("the beneficent philosopher")—in fact, an independent thinker whose views on culturewere in advance of Jean-Jacques Rousseau's, and who was the first to introduce into Polish intellectual life on a large scale the Frenchinfluences that were later to become so strong.[26]

Enlightenment

After a decline of a century and a half, in the mid-18th century, Polish philosophy began to revive. The hub of this movement was Warsaw. While Poland's capital then had no institution of higher learning, neither were those of Kraków, Zamośćor Wilnoany longer agencies of progress. The initial impetus for the revival came from religious thinkers: from members of the Piaristand other teaching orders. A leading patron of the new ideas was BishopAndrzej Stanisław Załuski.[24]Scholasticism, which until then had dominated Polish philosophy, was followed by the Enlightenment. Initially the major influence was Christian Wolffand, indirectly, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. The Polish-Lithuanian Commonwealth's electedking, August III the Saxon, and the relations between Poland and her neighbor, Saxony, heightened the Germaninfluence. Wolff's doctrine was brought to Warsaw in 1740 by the Theatine, Portalupi; from 1743, its chief Polish champion was Wawrzyniec Mitzler de Kolof(1711–78), court physician to August III.[27]Under the Polish-Lithuanian Commonwealth's last king, Stanisław August Poniatowski(reigned 1764–95), the Polish Enlightenmentwas radicalized and came under Frenchinfluence. The philosophical foundation of the movement ceased to be the Rationalistdoctrine of Wolff and became the Sensualismof Condillac. This spirit pervaded Poland's Commission of National Education, which completed the reforms begun by the Piaristpriest, Stanisław Konarski. The Commission's members were in touch with the French Encyclopedistsand freethinkers, with d'Alembertand Condorcet, Condillacand Rousseau. The Commission abolished school instruction in theology, even in philosophy.[28]This empiricistand positivistEnlightenment philosophy produced several outstanding Polish thinkers. Though active in the reign of Stanisław August Poniatowski, they published their chief works only after the loss of the Polish-Lithuanian Commonwealth's independence in 1795. The most important of these figures were Jan Śniadecki, Stanisław Staszicand Hugo Kołłątaj.[29]Another adherent of this empirical Enlightenment philosophy was the minister of education under the Duchy of Warsawand under the Congress Polandestablished by the Congress of Vienna, Stanisław Kostka Potocki(1755–1821). In some places, as at Krzemieniecand its Lyceumin southeastern Poland, this philosophy was to survive well into the nineteenth century. Though a belated philosophy from a western perspective, it was at the same time the philosophy of the future. This was the period between d'Alembertand Comte; and even as this variety of positivismwas temporarily fading in the West, it was carrying on in Poland.[30]At the turn of the nineteenth century, as Immanuel Kant's fame was spreading over the rest of Europe, in Poland the Enlightenment philosophy was still in full flower. Kantism found here a hostile soil. Even before Kant had been understood, he was condemned by the most respected writers of the time: by Jan Śniadecki, Staszic, Kołłątaj, Tadeusz Czacki, later by Anioł Dowgird(1776–1835). Jan Śniadeckiwarned against this "fanatical, dark and apocalyptic mind," and wrote: "To revise Lockeand Condillac, to desire a prioriknowledge of things that human nature can grasp only by their consequences, is a lamentable aberration of mind."[31]Jan Śniadecki's younger brother, however, Jędrzej Śniadecki, was the first respected Polish scholar to declare (1799) for Kant. And in applying Kantian ideas to the natural sciences, he did something new that would not be undertaken until much later by Johannes Müller, Hermann Ludwig Ferdinand von Helmholtzand other famous scientists of the nineteenth century.[32]Another Polish proponent of Kantism was Józef Kalasanty Szaniawski(1764–1843), who had been a student of Kant's at Königsberg. But, having accepted the fundamental points of the critical theory of knowledge, he still hesitated between Kant's metaphysical agnosticism and the new metaphysics of Idealism. Thus this one man introduced to Poland both the antimetaphysical Kant and the post-Kantian metaphysics.[33]In time, Kant's foremost Polish sympathizer would be Feliks Jaroński(1777–1827), who lectured at Kraków in 1809-18. Still, his Kantian sympathies were only partial. And this half-heartedness was typical of Polish Kantism generally. In Poland there was no actual Kantian period.[34]For a generation, between the age of the French Enlightenmentand that of the Polish national metaphysic, the Scottish philosophy of common sensebecame the dominant outlook in Poland. At the beginning of the nineteenth century, the Scottish School of Common Senseheld sway in most European countries—in Britain till mid-century, and nearly as long in France. But in Poland, from the first, the Scottish philosophy fused with Kantism, in this regard anticipating the West.[35]The Kantian and Scottish ideas were united in typical fashion by Jędrzej Śniadecki(1768–1838). The younger brother of Jan Śniadecki, Jędrzej was an illustrious scientist, biologist and physician, and the more creative mind of the two. He had been educated at the universities of Kraków, Paduaand Edinburghand was from 1796 a professor at Wilno, where he held a chair of chemistryand pharmacy. He was a foe of metaphysics, holding that the fathoming of first causesof beingwas "impossible to fulfill and unnecessary." But foe of metaphysics that he was, he was not an Empiricist—and this was his link with Kant. "Experiment and observation can only gather... the materials from which common sensealone can build science."[36]An analogous position, shunning both positivismand metaphysical speculation, affined to the Scots but linked in some features to Kantian critique, was held in the period before the November 1830 Uprisingby virtually all the university professors in Poland: in Wilno, by Dowgird; in Kraków, by Józef Emanuel Jankowski(1790–1847); and in Warsaw, by Adam Ignacy Zabellewicz(1784–1831) and Krystyn Lach Szyrma(1791–1866).[37]

Messianism

In the early nineteenth century, following a generation imbued with Enlightenment ideas, Poland passed directly to a maximal philosophical program, to absolute metaphysics, to syntheses, to great systems, to reform of the world through philosophy; and broke with positivism, the doctrines of the Enlightenment, and the precepts of Common Sense.[38]

The Polish metaphysical blossoming occurred between the November 1830 and January 1863 Uprisings, and stemmed from the spiritual aspirations of a politically humiliated people.[38]

The Poles' metaphysic, though drawing on German Idealism, differed considerably from it; it was Spiritualist rather than Idealist. It was characterized by a theistic belief in a personal God, in the everlastingness of souls, and in the superiority of spiritual over corporeal forces.[38]

The Polish metaphysic saw the mission of philosophy not only in the search for truth, but in the reformation of life and in the salvation of mankind. It was permeated with a faith in the metaphysical import of the nation and convinced that man could fulfill his vocation only within the communion of spirits that was the nation, that nations determined the evolution of mankind, and more particularly that the Polish nation had been assigned the role of Messiah to the nations.[38]

It was these three traits—the founding of a metaphysic on the concept of the soul and on the concept of the nation, and the assignment to the latter of reformative-soteriological tasks—that distinguished the Polish metaphysicians. Some, such as Hoene-Wroński, saw the Messiah in philosophy itself; others, such as the poet Mickiewicz, saw Him in the Polish nation. Hence Hoene-Wroński, and later Mickiewicz, adopted for their doctrines the name, "Messianism." It came to apply generically to Polish metaphysics of the nineteenth century, much as the term "Idealism" does to German metaphysics.[39]

In the first half of the nineteenth century, there appeared in Poland a host of metaphysicians unanimous as to these basic precepts, if strikingly at variance as to details. Their only center was Paris, which hosted Józef Maria Hoene-Wroński (1778–1853). Otherwise they lived in isolation: Bronisław Trentowski (1808–69) in Germany; Józef Gołuchowski (1797–1858) in Congress Poland; August Cieszkowski (1814–94) and Karol Libelt (1807–75) in Wielkopolska (western Poland); Józef Kremer (1806–75) in Kraków. Most of them became active only after the November 1830 Uprising.[40]

An important role in the Messianist movement was also played by the Polish Romantic poets, Adam Mickiewicz (1798–1855), Juliusz Słowacki (1809–49) and Zygmunt Krasiński (1812–59), as well as religious activists such as Andrzej Towiański (1799–1878).[39]

Between the philosophers and the poets, the method of reasoning, and often the results, differed. The poets desired to create a specifically Polish philosophy, the philosophers—an absolute universal philosophy. The Messianist philosophers knew contemporary European philosophy and drew from it; the poets created more of a home-grown metaphysic.[41]

The most important difference among the Messianists was that some were rationalists, others—mystics. Wroński's philosophy was no less rationalist than Hegel's, while the poets voiced a mystical philosophy.[39]

The Messianists were not the only Polish philosophers active in the period between the 1830 and 1863 Uprisings. Much more widely known in Poland were Catholic thinkers such as Father Piotr Semenenko (1814–86), Florian Bochwic (1779–1856) and Eleonora Ziemięcka (1819–69), Poland's first woman philosopher. The Catholic philosophy of the period was more widespread and fervent than profound or creative.[42]

Also active were pure Hegelians such as Tytus Szczeniowski (1808–80) and leftist Hegelians such as Edward Dembowski (1822–46).[43]

An outstanding representative of the philosophy of Common Sense, Michał Wiszniewski (1794–1865), had studied at that Enlightenment bastion, Krzemieniec; in 1820, in France, had attended the lectures of Victor Cousin; and in 1821, in Britain, had met the head of the Scottish School of Common Sense at the time, Dugald Stewart.[44]

Active as well were precursors of Positivism such as Józef Supiński (1804–93) and Dominik Szulc (1797–1860)—links between the earlier Enlightenment age of the brothers Śniadecki and the coming age of Positivism.[45]

Positivism

The Positivistphilosophy that took form in Poland after the January 1863 Uprisingwas hardly identical with the philosophy of Auguste Comte. It was in fact a return to the line of Jan Śniadeckiand Hugo Kołłątaj—a line that had remained unbroken even during the Messianist period—now enriched with the ideas of Comte.[46]However, it belonged only partly to philosophy. It combined Comte's ideas with those of John Stuart Milland Herbert Spencer, for it was interested in what was common to them all: a sober, empiricalattitude to life.[47]The Polish Positivism was a reaction against philosophical speculation, but also against romanticismin poetry and idealismin politics. It was less a scholarly movement than literary, politicaland social. Few original books were published, but many were translated from the philosophical literature of the West—not Comte himself, but easier writers: Hippolyte Taine, Mill, Spencer, Alexander Bain, Thomas Henry Huxley, the Germans Wilhelm Wundtand Friedrich Albert Lange, the Danish philosopher Höffding.[46]The disastrous outcome of the January 1863 Uprisinghad produced a distrust of romanticism, an aversion to ideals and illusions, and turned the search for redemption toward sober thought and work directed at realistic goals. The watchword became "organic work"—a term for the campaign for economic improvement, which was regarded as a prime requisite for progress. Poles prepared for such work by studying the natural sciencesand economics: they absorbed Charles Darwin's biological theories, Mill's economictheories, Henry Thomas Buckle's deterministictheory of civilization. At length they became aware of the connection between their own convictions and aims and the Positivistphilosophy of Auguste Comte, and borrowed its name and watchwords.[48]This movement, which had begun still earlier in Austrian-ruled Galicia, became concentrated with time in the Russian-ruled Congress Polandcentered about Warsawand is therefore commonly known as the "Warsaw Positivism."[49]Its chief venue was the Warsaw Przegląd Tygodniowy(Weekly Review);[48]Warsaw University(the "Main School") had been closed by the Russiansin 1869. The pioneers of the Warsaw Positivism were natural scientistsand physiciansrather than philosophers, and still more so journalistsand men of letters: Aleksander Świętochowski(1849–1938), Piotr Chmielowski(1848–1904), Adolf Dygasiński(1839–1902),[50]Bolesław Prus(1847–1912). Prus developed an original Utilitarian-inspired ethicalsystem in his book, The Most General Life Ideals.[51]The movement's leader was Prus' friend, Julian Ochorowicz(1850–1917), a trained philosopher with a doctorate from the University of Leipzig. In 1872 he wrote: "We shall call a Positivist, anyone who bases assertions on verifiable evidence; who does not express himself categorically about doubtful things, and does not speak at all about those that are inaccessible."[48]The Warsaw Positivists—who included faithful Catholicssuch as Father Franciszek Krupiński(1836–98)—formed a common front against Messianism together with the Neo-Kantians. The Polish Kantianswere rather loosely associated with Kant and belonged to the Positivist movement. They included Władysław Mieczysław Kozłowski(1858–1935), Piotr Chmielowski(1848–1904) and Marian Massonius(1862–1945).[52]The most brilliant philosophical mind in this period was Adam Mahrburg(1855–1913). He was a Positivistin his understanding of philosophy as a discipline and in his uncompromising ferreting out of speculation, and a Kantianin his interpretation of mind and in his centering of philosophy upon the theory of knowledge.[53]In Kraków, Father Stefan Pawlicki(1839–1916), professor of philosophy at the University of Kraków, was a man of broad culture and philosophical bent, but lacked talent for writing or teaching. Under his thirty-plus-year tenure, Kraków philosophy became mainly a historical discipline, alien to what was happening in the West and in Warsaw.[54]

20th century

Even before Poland regained independence at the end of World War I, her intellectual life continued to develop. This was the case particularly in Russian-ruled Warsaw, where in lieu of underground lectures and secret scholarly organizations a Wolna Wszechnica Polska(Free Polish University) was created in 1905 and the tireless Władysław Weryho(1868–1916) had in 1898 founded Poland's first philosophical journal, Przegląd Filozoficzny(The Philosophical Review), and in 1904 a Philosophical Society.[55]In 1907 Weryho founded a Psychological Society, and subsequently Psychological and Philosophical Institutes. About 1910 the small number of professionally trained philosophers increased sharply, as individuals returned who had been inspired by Mahrburg's underground lectures to study philosophy in Austrian-ruled Lwówand Krakówor abroad.[55]Krakówas well, especially after 1910, saw a quickening of the philosophical movement, particularly at the Polish Academy of Learning, where at the prompting of Władysław Heinrichthere came into being in 1911 a Committee for the History of Polish Philosophy and there was an immense growth in the number of philosophical papers and publications, no longer only of a historicalcharacter.[56]At Lwów, Kazimierz Twardowskifrom 1895 stimulated a lively philosophical movement, in 1904 founded the Polish Philosophical Society,[57]and in 1911 began publication of Ruch Filozoficzny(The Philosophical Movement).[56]There was growing interest in western philosophical currents, and much discussion of Pragmatismand Bergsonism, psychoanalysis, Henri Poincaré's Conventionalism, Edmund Husserl's Phenomenology, the Marburg School, and the social-sciencemethodologiesof Wilhelm Diltheyand Heinrich Rickert. At the same time, original ideas developed on Polish soil.[56]Those who distinguished themselves in Polish philosophy in these pre-World War Iyears of the twentieth century, formed two groups. One group developed apart from institutions of higher learningand learned societies, and appealed less to trained philosophers than to broader circles, which it (if but briefly) captured. It constituted a reaction against the preceding period of Positivism, and included Stanisław Brzozowski(1878–1911), Wincenty Lutosławski(1863–1954) and, to a degree, Edward Abramowski(1868–1918).[58]The second group of philosophers who started off Polish philosophy in the twentieth century had an academiccharacter. They included Władysław Heinrich(1869–1957) in Kraków, Kazimierz Twardowski(1866–1938) in Lwów, and Leon Petrażycki(1867–1931) abroad—all three, active members of the Polish Academy of Learning. Despite the considerable differences among them, they shared some basic features: all three were empiricistsconcerned not with metaphysics but with the foundations of philosophy; they were interested in philosophy itself, not merely its history; they understood philosophy in positive terms, but none of them was a Positivist in the old style.[59]Following the restoration of Poland's independence in 1918, the two older universities (Kraków University, Lwów University) were joined by four new ones (Warsaw University, Poznań University, Wilno University, Lublin University). New philosophical journals appeared; all the university cities formed philosophical associations; conventions of Polish philosophers were held; philosophy became more professional, academic, scholarly.[60]A characteristic of the interbellumwas that maximalist, metaphysical currents began to fade away.[61]The dominant ambition in philosophical theory now was not breadth but precision. This was a period of specialization, consistent with the conviction that general philosophy would not yield precise results such as could be obtained in logic, psychologyor the history of philosophy.[62]A few individuals did develop a general philosophical outlook: notably, Tadeusz Kotarbiński(1886–1981), Stanisław Ignacy Witkiewicz(1885–1939), and Roman Ingarden(1893–1970).[63]Otherwise, however, specializationwas the rule. The Kraków school, true to tradition, showed an eminently historical character and produced a medievalistof world renown, Father Konstanty Michalski(1879–1947).[64]The Lwów school concentrated on the analysis of concepts; and in doing so, it considered both their aspects, the subjectiveand objective—hence, the psychologicaland the logical. Twardowski himself continued working at the border of psychology and logic; his pupils, however, generally split in their interests, specializing in either psychology or logic.[62]The analyticalprogram that Twardowski passed on to his pupils, and which they in turn spread throughout Poland, was affined to that of Franz Brentano's school (Twardowski's alma mater) in Austriaand to that of the Britishanalytic school, which likewise had arisen as a reaction against speculativesystems.[65]The alumniof the Lwów school entered three distinct fields. Some devoted themselves to psychology: Stefan Błachowski(1889–1962), professor at Poznań, entirely; Władysław Witwicki(1878–1948), professor at Warsaw, partly. Others pursued the theory of knowledge: they included Kazimierz Ajdukiewicz(1890–1963), professor at Lwów, and after World War IIat Poznań, whose views resembled Neopositivismand who developed an original theory of radical Conventionalism. The third group worked in mathematical, or symbolic, logic.[64]The most important center for mathematical logic was Warsaw. The Warsaw school of logic was headed by Jan Łukasiewicz(1878–1956) and Stanisław Leśniewski(1886–1939), professors at Warsaw University, and the first of their pupils to achieve eminence, even before World War II, was Alfred Tarski(1902–83),[64]from 1939 in the United States, where he became a professor at the University of California, Berkeley; another pupil of Łukasiewicz, Bolesław Sobociński, became a professor at the University of Notre Dame. The Warsaw logic gained a worldwide importance similar to that of the Kraków medievalism.[64]Warsaw was not, however, the sole Polish venue for logic studies. These were initiated at Krakówby the mathematics professor, Jan Sleszyński. At Kraków, too, and later at Lwów, they were conducted by Leon Chwistek(1884–1944), a multi-faceted and somewhat eccentric thinker—mathematician, philosopher, esthetician, painter—whose name came to be associated popularly with his concept of "plural realities."[66]After Petrażycki's death, the outstanding legalphilosopher was Czesław Znamierowski(1888–1967), professor of philosophy at Poznań.[67]Another leading thinker of the period, active on the borderlines of sociologyand philosophy, in both Polandand the United States, was Florian Znaniecki(1882–1958).[68]In the interbellum, the philosopher members of the Polish Academy of Learningincluded Heinrich(Kraków), Kazimierz Twardowski(Lwów), Leon Petrażycki(Warsaw), and, from the following generation: Konstanty Michalski, Jan Łukasiewiczand Władysław Tatarkiewicz(1886–1980). Michalski's historical works revolutionized prevailing views on via modernain late medieval philosophy. Łukasiewicz gained world fame with his concept of many-valued logicand is known for his "Polish notation." Tatarkiewicz was the first to prepare in Polisha large-scale comprehensive history of western philosophyand a History of Aestheticsand worked at systematizing the conceptsof estheticsand ethics.[69]After World War II, Roman Ingarden, Tadeusz Kotarbińskiand Alfred Tarskibecame members of the Academy.[3]For some four decades following World War II, in Poland, a disproportionately prominent official role was given to Marxist philosophy. This, and contemporaneous sociopolitical currents, stimulated Leszek Kołakowski, writing in exile, to publish influential critiques of Marxisttheory and communistpractice. Kołakowski also wrote a remarkable history of Positivist Philosophy from Hume to the Vienna Circle.[70]Similarly notable for his critiques of SovietMarxismwas Józef Maria Bocheński, O.P., a Catholicphilosopher of the Dominican Orderwho lectured in Romeat the Pontifical University of Saint Thomas Aquinas(the Angelicum) and at the University of Fribourgin Switzerland. Bocheński also gained renown for his work in logicand ethics. Other Polish philosophers of the postwar period included Andrzej Zabłudowski, who engaged in polemics with Nelson Goodman; and Marek Siemek, a historian of GermanTranscendental Philosophyand recipient of an honorary doctoratefrom Bonn University.

See also

Notes

  1. ^ Władysław Tatarkiewicz, Zarys dziejów filozofii w Polsce (A Brief History of Philosophy in Poland), p. 32.
  2. ^ Władysław Tatarkiewicz, Historia filozofii (History of Philosophy), vol. 3, p. 177.
  3. ^ a b Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., p. 32.
  4. ^ Kazimierz Kuratowski, A Half Century of Polish Mathematics, pp. 23-24, 33.
  5. ^ Kazimierz Kuratowski, A Half Century of Polish Mathematics, p. 30 and passim.
  6. ^ a b Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., p. 5.
  7. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., p. 5.
  8. ^ Will Durant, The Age of Faith, p. 1011.
  9. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., pp. 5–6.
  10. ^ a b c d e Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., p. 6.
  11. ^ a b Tatarkiewicz, Historia filozofii, vol. 1, p. 311.
  12. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Historia filozofii, vol. 1, pp. 303–4.
  13. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., pp. 6–7.
  14. ^ a b Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., p. 7.
  15. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., pp. 7–8.
  16. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., pp. 7-8.
  17. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., p. 8.
  18. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., pp. 8–9.
  19. ^ a b c d Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., p. 9.
  20. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., pp. 9–10.
  21. ^ a b Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., p. 10.
  22. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Historia filozofii, vol. 2, p. 38.
  23. ^ Joseph Kasparek, The Constitutions of Poland and of the United States: Kinships and Genealogy, pp. 245–50.
  24. ^ a b c Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., p. 11.
  25. ^ Kasparek, The Constitutions..., pp. 218–24.
  26. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., p. 11.
  27. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., pp. 11–12.
  28. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., p. 12.
  29. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., pp. 12–13.
  30. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., p. 13.
  31. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., p. 14.
  32. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Historia filozofii, vol. 2, pp. 187–88.
  33. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., pp. 14–15.
  34. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., p. 15.
  35. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., pp. 15–16.
  36. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Historia filozofii, vol. 2, p. 189.
  37. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., pp. 16-17.
  38. ^ a b c d Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., p. 17.
  39. ^ a b c Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., p. 18.
  40. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Historia filozofii, vol. 2, p. 229.
  41. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Zarys, p. 18.
  42. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Historia filozofii, vol. 3, p. 173.
  43. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., p. 24.
  44. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Historia filozofii, vol. 3, p. 174.
  45. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., p. 24. Tatarkiewicz, Historia filozofii, vol. 3, p. 175.
  46. ^ a b Tatarkiewicz, Historia filozofii, vol. 3, p. 176.
  47. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., p. 25.
  48. ^ a b c Tatarkiewicz, Historia filozofii, vol. 3, p. 177.
  49. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., pp. 25–26.
  50. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Historia filozofii, vol. 3, p. 177.
  51. ^ Edward Pieścikowski, Bolesław Prus, pp. 138-39.
  52. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Historia filozofii, vol. 3, pp. 177–78.
  53. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Historia filozofii, vol. 3, pp. 177-78.
  54. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Historia filozofii, vol. 3, p. 175.
  55. ^ a b Tatarkiewicz, Historia filozofii, vol. 3, p. 356.
  56. ^ a b c Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., p. 27.
  57. ^ "Twardowski, Kazimierz," Encyklopedia powszechna PWN, vol. 4, p. 512.
  58. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., pp. 27–28.
  59. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., pp. 29-30.
  60. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Historia filozofii, vol. 3, pp. 363–64.
  61. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., p. 30.
  62. ^ a b Tatarkiewicz, Historia filozofii, vol. 3, p. 366.
  63. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., pp. 30–31.
  64. ^ a b c d Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., p. 31.
  65. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Historia filozofii, vol. 3, p. 368.
  66. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Historia filozofii, vol. 3, p. 367.
  67. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Historia filozofii, vol. 3, pp. 367–68.
  68. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Historia filozofii, vol. 3, p. 361.
  69. ^ Tatarkiewicz, Zarys..., pp. 31–32.
  70. ^ Leszek Kołakowski, Positivist Philosophy from Hume to the Vienna Circle, Penguin Books, 1972, ASIN B000OIXO7E.

References

External links

   Return to top of page.